Tag Archives: the Problem of Evil

PHILOSOPHICAL AND BILBICAL RESPONSES TO CLASSIC ARGUMENTS FROM EVIL

CLASSICAL ARUGMENTS FROM EVIL

Although the story recounted in the book of Job is not the oldest story portrayed in the Bible, the book Job itself, it is argued,[1] is the oldest of the divinely inspired canonical texts[2].  Fittingly, the protagonist of that book, Job the Uzzite, and his friends grapple with one of mankind’s oldest problems, the problem of evil. Through no fault of his own, Job suffers the loss of vast amounts of wealth, failing health, and the death of all his children.[3] A major theme of the book is how he and his friends cope with and try to understand the tragic events that have befallen him.  God’s role in and possible culpability for the horrible events in Job’s life, among other issues, are called into question.  Tragic situations like that of Job are hardly unique to him.  Mankind as a whole is beset by evil and ever-beleaguered by the negative experiences that accompany its manifestation.  Experiences like those of Job raise a classical philosophical quandary: “Is God willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then he is impotent.  Is he able, but not willing?  Then he is malevolent.  Is he both able and willing?  Whence then is evil?”[4]

Enlightenment Philosopher, David Hume, credited the phrasing of this question to the ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus.[5]  This question, as formulated by Epicurus,[6] is one of the oldest recorded statements about evil as it relates to God in Western thought. A more recent statement on this classical philosophical quandary, which has become formally known as “The Problem from Evil,” was formulated by philosopher of religion J.L. Mackie.  According to Mackie, the problem from Evil[7] in its simplest form is this: “God is omnipotent, God is wholly good; and yet evil exists.”[8] This is a sobering statement; one that shakes the faith of many.  The Problem from Evil makes it seem as if theistic belief (in a wholly good, omnipotent God) contradicts itself.  Throughout the years, the simple problem from evil identified by Mackie and Epicurus has been challenged, rethought, and, perhaps as a result challenges, evolved into various, more nuanced arguments from evil.  Three such classical arguments from evil that every Christian apologist should understand and be prepared to refute are:[9] (1) The Logical Argument from Evil, (2) The Probabilistic Argument from Evil, (3) and the Argument from Gratuitous Evil.  These arguments can be refuted philosophically (using general revelation) as well as biblically (using special revelation); the Christian apologist should be prepared to use both general and special revelation to make a defense for the hope that is within him.[10]  Before engaging these arguments from evil, the apologist must also be acquainted with two understandings (or categories) of evil: (1) natural evil and (2) moral evil.  Furthermore, he must be wary of the temptation to engage in refutations of these arguments that are less than biblical for the sake of defeating them.  Scripture and general revelation provide avenues by which these arguments can be refuted in ways that are faithful to the biblical text and respectful of God’s perfect nature.

MORAL EVIL AND NATURAL EVIL

 “Evil comes in a plethora of types and instances, but the field divides into two categories: natural evil and human evil.  Natural evil is the natural world turned savage: tornadoes, earthquakes, tidal waves, hurricanes, floods. Diseases and deformity fill out this category, since they are not usually instigated by humans…Then there is evil from human hands (moral evil). It comes from the gun, the knife, the bomb, the pen and the tongue.”[11] Arguments from evil and the theodicies by which they are refuted interact with one or both of these categories of evil.  For example, in the minds of some, a soul-building theodicy may be a more plausible defense against an argument from natural evil than a free will theodicy. Thus, being able to identify the categories of evil to which various arguments from evil refer is very important to understanding them.  Unless, that is, one denies the existence of evil altogether. The idea that evil does not exist was popularized by Augustine. According to Augustine, evil is the result of the improper function of God’s creations, the result of the improper use of the free will which God has granted to his created beings.  These created beings all have their place in God’s ordered creation and sometimes evil is caused by their actions, whether it be natural evil (like a lion eating a baby) or moral evil (Satan rebelling against God).  In that sense, evil does not truly exist but is merely a privation of good.  For those who insist that evil does exist, it is generally understood in the two categories mentioned above.

GOD OR EVIL: THE LOGICAL ARGUMENT FROM EVIL

The logical argument from Evil is designed to show that the existence of an omnipotent, wholly good God is incompatible with the existence of evil.  It asks the question, if God is wholly good and created everything, how could evil exist?  It seems illogical that a good God would have (or even could have) created a world in which evil exists.  If one proposes that an all-powerful, all-knowing, entirely good God exists, he makes a logical contradiction if he proposes that evil exists as well.  Since evil clearly exists, according to the logical argument from evil, there cannot be such a God.  There are several different flavors of the logical argument from evil, each denies the theistic position.  J.L. Mackie’s simple statement, mentioned in the “Introduction” section above, is the most straightforward:

  • An omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good God exists
  • Evil exists

Theists don’t necessarily see these positions as contradictory. Therefore, it us up to the atheistic critic to point out that they are.  No matter how well an atheist may argue, he is not able to do so.  Theists agree with atheists that it is illogical for one to hold contradictory beliefs[12] but deny that the logical argument from evil presents contrary positions.

A Free Will Defense and a Soul-Building Theodicy

Theists believe that one can believe in an omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good God and believe that He created a world in which there is evil without engaging in a logical contradiction.  This belief is supported by The Free Will Defense, which proposes that God created a world in which beings have the capacity to choose to perform morally good actions or morally evil actions.  If God did not create such a world, there would be no moral value.  In other words, there cannot be a capacity for good unless there is a capacity for evil.  Beings have the free will to choose to do good or evil; sometimes beings will freely choose to do evil.  Any other state of affairs would render the world valueless.  Furthermore, God cannot be held morally responsible for this state of affairs, nor can His nonexistence be logically deduced from it given that “God cannot both create free beings and determine what they freely do.”[13]  J.L. Mackie himself, in the face of a Free Will defense admitted that the Problem from Evil does not demonstrate that theism is contradictory by stating “we can concede that the problem (from) evil does not, after all, show that the central doctrines of theism are logically inconsistent with one another.”[14] Mackie is not the only person who has rejected his thesis.  “It is almost universally agreed that evil is logically compatible with the existence of God.”[15]

The Free Will defense, while sufficient, is not the only formidable refutation of the logical argument from evil. The soul-building theodicy of John Hick also counters this argument.  Hick’s soul-building argument posits that God has a plan and purpose for the world; God’s plan involves a growth and development for humans in which they should overcome evil.  Hick argued that the evil in the world that causes it to appear that God does not exist imparts value on the faith of those who believe He does.  The evil in the world helps those who overcome it build their souls. God’s purpose in allowing evil is soul-building; evil is the fire through which the metal of the soul is heated so that it may be hammered into its proper form.

A Biblical Response from Free Will

Evil exists, to summarize the free will discussion above, because God allows people freedom of choice; if people did not have the ability to choose to do right or wrong, life would essentially be meaningless.  Evil exists because God allows people the choice to be evil or do evil.  Thus, evil doesn’t come from a wholly good God but from humanity, whom God endowed with free will.  This is an adequate explanation for the existence of “moral” evil (i.e., murder, theft, rape) levied by humans against other humans; however, it does not provide an adequate explanation for the existence of “natural” evil (i.e. earthquakes, tsunamis, and tornadoes) levied by nature.  Humans can’t cause earthquakes and storms[16]; natural evils are not seemingly caused by free decisions.  However, the existence of natural evil in a world created by a wholly good God can still be justified.  One such justification is that that natural evils are indeed caused by free choice; not the free choice of humans but the free choice of lower supernatural beings (i.e. the devil and demons).  Another justification is that the potential for natural evil is the result of original sin which was brought about by the free will of Adam.  There are biblical passages to support these assertions.

In the book of Job, God allows Satan to test the faithfulness of the righteous and wealthy Job by giving Satan permission to take away everything the wealthy man has but his life.  Satan takes away Job’s wealth by various methods, which include natural evil.  While Job is being informed by the third of three messengers that all his livestock has been lost in a series of raids by hostile tribes, a fourth messenger arrives to inform him that his children have been killed: “While he was still speaking, another also came and said, ‘Your sons and your daughters were eating and drinking wine in their oldest brother’s house, and behold, a great wind came from across the wilderness and struck the four corners of the house, and it fell on the young people and they died, and I alone have escaped to tell you’”[17]  Job’s children are slain by a natural evil, a “mighty wind.”  The destructive wind was not caused by random weather patterns; it was intentionally caused by Satan for the sole purpose of heaping misfortune upon Job.  Satan can cause natural evil.  The book of Job doesn’t go as far to report that Satan causes every single instance of natural evil, but it does show that he does have the power to cause such evil.  This in itself grants validity to the free will defense that natural evil is perhaps caused by the choice of supernatural beings other than God, such as Satan or demons.[18]

In his epistle to the Romans, Paul provides a foundation for the doctrine of original sin and its role in the existence of death.  Paul states, “Therefore, just as through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin, and so death spread to all men, because all sinned— for until the Law sin was in the world, but sin is not imputed when there is no law. Nevertheless death reigned from Adam until Moses, even over those who had not sinned in the likeness of the offense of Adam, who is a type of Him who was to come.”[19]  According to Paul, death came to everyone because of Adam’s original sin.  Because of original sin, mankind can die.  Being so cursed, man is subject to the calamities of natural evil.  Obviously, all natural evils do not cause death.  Every tornado or hurricane doesn’t kill a human, it may just destroy property.  However, just because a natural evil doesn’t cause immediate death does not mean that its occurrence is not a repercussion of original sin.  The curse upon man caused by original sin facilitates more than death alone.  In the Garden of Eden, Adam came by his sustenance in a leisurely manner.  Because of the curse, mankind is relegated to eking out a living by “the sweat of his brow.”[20]   In the Garden of Evil, Adam didn’t need a sustainable shelter, farm, or even clothing.  After the fall, because of the curse, such things are needed by man.  Thus, natural evils can destroy property without creating incongruence between God’s goodness and his omnipotence.

A Biblical Response from Soul-Building

Evil in whatever form it exists is a necessary evil.  In simpler words, if everything was all sunshine and rainbows, no one would appreciate sunshine and rainbows.  In effect, a world replete with evil serves as a crucible in which the human soul can spiritually mature. The following biblical passages support the notion that the endurance of evil gives value to the Christian life:  Romans 5:1-5 and 1 Peter 4:12-19.

According to Paul, Christians rejoice in their sufferings because suffering (which is surely considered “an evil”) indirectly produces hope.  Paul states, “…we also exult in our tribulations, knowing that tribulation bring about perseverance; and perseverance, proven character; and proven character, hope; and hope does not disappoint, because the love of God has been poured out within our hearts through the Holy Spirit who was given to us.”[21]  Paul was writing to Christians in Rome who were indeed suffering.  They were subject to persecution from Romans of both Gentile and Jewish heritage for their dedication to Christ.  In any age and under any circumstance (no matter how dire); the Christian who perseveres builds spiritual character.  Through this character he can understand that his ultimate hope is deliverance through the Holy Spirit.  This deliverance does not necessarily have to manifest itself in the present age, but is more accurately considered to be a hope for deliverance in the age to come.  The sufferings of the world and its evils pale in comparison to the sufferings of the eternal damnation of hell.  The evil in the world helps Christians come to this understanding by indirectly building their character.  Without the presence of that evil, Christians would not truly understand the great gift they have received in the Holy Spirit.

Paul’s associate, Peter, echoes his sentiments in 1 Peter.  Peter specifically orders his Christian audience not to be perplexed by the evil that surrounds them.  He tells them “do not be surprised at the fiery ordeal among you, which comes upon you for your testing, as though some strange thing were happening to you.”[22]  This statement endorses a viewpoint that starkly contrasts that of one who subscribes to a Problem-from-Evil-atheistic philosophy.  This kind of atheist doubts the existence of God based upon his perception of evil in the world.  Peter, on the other hand, sees the suffering of evil as by-product of a dedication to God.  Christ suffered and Christians are to rejoice in their opportunity to share in that suffering.  Peter sees suffering as a badge of honor to be pinned upon one’s chest by God himself.  Peter states, “…those also who suffer according to the will of God shall entrust their souls to a faithful Creator in doing what is right.”[23]

Both Paul and Peter observe that suffering is a part of the Christian life.  Suffering, of course, is not limited to Christians alone.  The unrighteous suffer as well, but to a different end and in a different way.  Peter delineates how the Christian should endure suffering, “Make sure that none of you suffers as a murderer, or thief, or evildoer, or a troublesome meddler; but if anyone suffers as a Christian, he is not to be ashamed, but is to glorify God in this name.”[24] This is the same type of character-building suffering, to which Paul refers.  It is the kind of suffering that builds hope.  The atheist has no hope in his heart.  When he suffers or sees suffering, he can only endure it the ways of the unrighteous.  The unrighteous will be judged by God just as the righteous will, but the outcome of the judgment will be very different.  The suffering Christian can hold out hope for eternal salvation, suffering to the conclusion that he is an heir to the Kingdom of God. The suffering atheist, who will not recognize God’s existence, endures suffering to the false conclusion that there is no God.  The Christian’s soul is “built” through suffering; the atheist or even the lost theist cannot relate to this.

GOD COULD DO BETTER: THE PROBABILISTIC ARGMENT FROM EVIL

Whereas the logical argument from evil operates by logically inferring something like, “One cannot say that there is no fire while he yet says there is smoke,” the probabilistic argument from evil infers something like, “One can say that since there is smoke, there is probably fire.”  The probabilistic argument from evil posits that the existence of evil in the world may not disprove God’s existence but it certainly makes it less probable.  Like the logical argument from evil, the probabilistic argument from evil exists in several different versions.  These different versions are based upon the following premises:

  • If God is all-powerful, all-knowing and wholly good, He could have created any possible world.
  • Therefore, if God is as such, He would have created the best of all possible worlds.
  • Because evil exists, it’s unlikely that the actual world is the best world that could have been created.
  • Therefore, it’s not likely that an all-powerful, all-knowing, and wholly good God exists.

This soundness of this argument depends on knowing what God would do and thus it fails; presuming knowledge of God’s hypothetical actions is an exercise in hubris.

A Theodicy from Subjectivity

The theistic counter-argument to this argument from evil notes that the data set from which to probabilistically deny God is incomplete or unidentifiable.  What exactly is the “best” of all possible worlds and who is qualified to make that assessment? A theist could just as easily make an argument that God probably does exist if he picked his own prejudiced data set.  Different people have different opinions on what the best of all worlds is, would, or could be.  Furthermore, different people have different opinions on what evil itself is.  It turns out that, because of the nature of subjectivity, the probabilistic argument from evil is its own defeater. Without God, in Whom humanity can ground objective moral values duties, all judgments as to what evil is are purely subjective. “If atheism is true, it becomes impossible to condemn war, oppression, or crime as evil. Nor can one praise brotherhood, equality, or love as good. It doesn’t matter what you do—for there is no right and wrong; all things are permitted.”[25]  “Whence then is evil?” becomes a vexing question for the atheist; for it is he who engages in affirming a contradiction.

A Biblical Response from Divine Objectivity

“Woe to those who call evil good, and good evil; Who substitute darkness for light and light for darkness; Who substitute bitter for sweet and sweet for bitter!  Woe to those who are wise in their own eyes and clever in their own sight!”[26] These words God spoke through the prophet Isaiah.  In His statements through Isaiah, God clearly asserts that there are those who reject God’s definition of what is evil while perceiving falsely perceiving themselves as clever.  The Apostle Paul paints a similar picture of such sinful people in the first chapter of his epistle to the Romans, writing, “…just as they did not see fit to acknowledge God any longer, God gave them over to a depraved mind, to do those things which are not proper…although they know the ordinance of God, that those who practice such things are worthy of death, they not only do the same, but also give hearty approval to those who practice them.”[27]  Those who reject God have such a depraved mind that they are led to approve wicked deeds.  Such men would assert that the world is a better place for the presence of these deeds, while God clearly and rightfully decries wicked deeds for what they are. When the atheist claims that God probably doesn’t exist because the world is not as good as he thinks it should be, he’s essentially saying, “God doesn’t exist because if He did, He would agree with me and do differently.” This argument is painfully subjective.

Without God, who is clearly identified by Jesus as the “only One who is good”,[28] there is absolutely no person in which an objective idea of what is best can be sufficiently grounded.  There can only be various men, who not only disagree with one another about what is best but are inherently flawed themselves,[29] in whom goodness can be subjectively grounded.  “The heart is more deceitful than all else and is desperately sick,”[30] declared the Lord through the prophet Jeremiah as he cursed those who “trust in mankind, make flesh their strength, and turn their hearts away from the Lord.”[31]  No man can provide proper grounding for objective good.  There simply exists no man who can rightly say, “God would have or should have done better,” for no man[32] can honestly declare that he was there when the world was created and that he knows best how it should have been made.[33]

BURNING BAMBI: THE GRATUTIOUS ARGUMENT FROM EVIL

The gratuitous argument from evil is based, not upon probabilities regarding the existence of evil, but upon the heinous nature of evil itself.  It states that some evil is so intense that its gratuitous nature casts the shadow of doubt upon God’s existence.  Philosopher William Rowe presented the argument from gratuitous evil as follows:

  • There exist instances of intense suffering which an omnipotent, omniscient being could have prevented without thereby losing some greater good or permitting some evil equally bad or worse. (In short, this kind of suffering as is gratuitous evil)
  • An omniscient, wholly good being would prevent the occurrence of any intense suffering it could, unless it could not do so without thereby losing some greater good god or permitting some evil equally bad or worse
  • There does not exist an omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good being.

To demonstrate premise 1, Rowe imagines a fawn perishing alone in a horrendous forest fire.  Rowe can’t imagine that      some greater good could come out of en event such as that; it is an instance of gratuitous evil.[34]  Despite the dramatic and powerful imagining of a helpless burning fawn, Rowe’s premise is faulty because it involves a non-omniscient being stating what an omniscient being would do in a given situation.  His argument is not only hindered because of subjectivity (similar to the way the probabilistic argument is hindered) but because of constraints.  Rowe and others who would declare an evil “gratuitous” can only do so from limited knowledge; from limited knowledge such persons cannot rightly reject the existence of a being, God, Who possesses unlimited knowledge.

A Theodicy from Constraints

Recognizing constraints, the theist can invalidate Rowe’s entire argument by countering this proposition by asking, “How can it be known that gratuitous evil exists?”  Maybe there is not such suffering which could have been prevented without allowing some equally heinous evil or preventing some equally effable good?   Maybe it just appears that way.  Here, the theist can fall back on the soul-building theodicy of John Hick.  However, “the most potent atheistic rebuttals to theistic specifications of greater goods revolve around the claim that at least some evils…do not seem necessary to any greater good.”[35] Thus, a soul-building theodicy may be unconvincing.

A rebuttal that avoids claims to “greater goods” is the best possible world theodicy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.  This argument concludes that God is simply not blame for the existence of evil in the world.  Leibniz made the case that this world is the best possible world that could have been created because God in his omnipotence and omniscience just wouldn’t have created a sub-par world.  Therefore, the evil that exists in world exists in the appropriate amounts and kinds; thus, it cannot be gratuitous. Like the baby’s bear’s porridge to Goldilocks, the evil in the world is “just right.”  This theodicy, however, is open to the retort that a good God just wouldn’t have created the actual world.  “If this is what ‘just right’ looks like, there is no God,” the atheist might argue.

To answer this objection, Alvin Plantinga tweaked Leibniz’s argument to consider, not what God wouldn’t have done, but what God couldn’t have done.  Plantinga argues, in a type of free will defense, for a concept he calls “transworld depravity.”[36]  According to this concept, possible worlds in which all free creatures always freely choose not to do evil are not feasible creations even for omnipotent being.  This situation does not impinge upon God’s omnipotence because it is logically impossible to create any world in which free creatures exist and evil does not.  Creating such a world would equate to creating a square circle or married bachelor.

The atheist who makes the argument from gratuitous evil fails to recognize the existence of constraints and tradeoffs: his own and God’s.  To conclude that one knows all possible reasons for which a “gratuitous” evil could be allowed is to presume something on the level of omniscience. Only God is omniscient. “As finite persons, we are limited in time, space, intelligence, and insight. But the transcendent and sovereign God sees the end from the beginning and providentially orders history so that His purposes are ultimately achieved through human free decisions. In order to achieve His ends, God may have to put up with certain evils along the way. Evils which appear pointless to us within our limited framework may be seen to have been justly permitted within God’s wider framework.”[37] Furthermore, the atheist who makes the argument from gratuitous evil (really any argument from evil) fails to recognize the existence of the contradiction of a world with evil and without God.  In effect, he wants to have his cake and eat it, too.  He denies the existence of God but affirms the existence of evil, which cannot objectively exist if God does not.

Whatever reason one concludes that evil is “gratuitous,” is ultimately subjective.  This subjectivity of opinion is best illustrated by what economist Thomas Sowell calls a conflict of visions. “Visions are foundations on which theories are built.  The final structure depends not only on the foundation, but also on how carefully and consistently the framework of theory is constructed and how well buttressed it is with hard facts.  Visions are clearly subjective, but well constructed theories have clear implications, and facts can test and measure their objective validity.”[38]  Sowell identifies two visions: the unconstrained vision and the constrained vision. Those who hold to the constrained vision see the world as a place that is full of tradeoffs, constraints, and unknownables. Those who hold to the unconstrained vision see the world as a place in which the best possible state of affairs can be identified and actualized by those with the intelligence and intellectual capacity to do so.   It is such people (to whom Sowell refers at the intelligentsia) who believe they can definitively determine what the best possible world would be and what any justifications for evil would be.  One must adhere to the unconstrained vision to stake his atheism in the foundation of gratuitous evil because in doing so believes that he, a finite man, can understand every exhaustive possibility. An atheist who wishes to rely on the Gratuitous Argument (or the Probabilistic Argument for that matter) must set his own, arbitrary definition of what the best possible world or gratuitous evil would look like and hold his definition of above that of anyone else who disagrees with him, despite the condition that there is no objective test by which to prove his view.

A Biblical Response from Constraints

Both the arguments that God does not exist because this world is probably not the best possible world and the argument that God does not exist because of the existence of gratuitous evil fall flat.  It is demonstrated from scripture that God did create the best (logically) possible world; however, it has been marred by human sin.  Scripture also makes it clear that humans have no place, in their limited human capacity, to judge God’s reasons for allowing evil.

God created the world perfectly and will one day restore it to perfection. The current world has been constrained by the fall. After God created the Earth and everything in it, he deemed it “very good.”[39]  God placed Adam and his wife Eve in the Garden of Eden; they had everything they needed.  Still, Adam and Eve made the choice to disobey God by eating the forbidden fruit of the Tree of Knowledge of Good and Evil, thus causing the fall.  Because of Adam and Eve’s choice to disobey God, they and their descendents were assured death[40].  Even the very ground of the earth itself was cursed because of their misdeed[41].  In assessing the fall, theologian Millard Erickson solemnly remarks, “We live in a world that God created, but it is not quite as it was when God finished it; it is now a fallen and broken world.”[42]  Man traverses a world that is literally cursed, whereas before the fall man abided in a state of peaceful existence.

As illustrated by the book of Job, whatever God’s reasons for allowing evil are, man is completely inept at identifying them.  Job’s friends Eliphaz, Bildad, and Zophar all offered Job theories as to why calamity had befallen him; each theory was incorrect.  God himself chided the men for arriving at the conclusions that they reached.  In Chapters 38 through 42, God exposes the depth of the ignorance of man, asking “Who is this that darkens counsel by words without knowledge?”[43] God presents and exhaustive series of questions that Job’s friends cannot possibly answer.  Man’s knowledge is limited.  Furthermore, his very ability to comprehend pales in comparison to that of God, who declares through the prophet Isaiah: “…My thoughts are not your thoughts, Nor are your ways My ways…For as the heavens are higher than the earth, So are My ways higher than your ways And My thoughts than your thoughts.”[44]

A CAVEAT AND A CONCLUSION

It is readily apparent when assessing the preceding review of classical arguments from evil that their refutations (both philosophical and biblical) can substantially overlap.  The consideration of subjectivity weakens both the probabilistic and gratuitous arguments from evil.  A free-will defense and a soul-building theodicy subvert both the logical and gratuitous arguments.  The fallen nature of man and creation, as described in the Bible, address all three arguments from evil in some way.  The biblical text provides the Christian apologist his strongest defenses available to arguments from evil.  However, the biblical text itself can present its own problems from evil, such as the Problem of Hell, which asserts that a good and loving God wouldn’t punish people with eternal torment.  Seeking to avoid such arguments, the apologist may be tempted to present the unbiblical notions of Christian universalism or annihilationism (even if he rejects them himself) to the unbeliever simply to refute the Problem of Hell.  He may be tempted to present other unbiblical positions to refute other objections to the biblical text as well.  The Apologist, when engaging with a person who is completely unwilling to consider the biblical text, is left only with philosophical arguments.  He can be similarly tempted to use biblically incompatible philosophical arguments to refute a problem from evil.  If a Christian takes an unbiblical position to avoid the implications of a given problem from evil, he wins the battle only to lose the war.

It is one thing to insist that there are logically impossible things that God can’t do, such as force a person to freely do something.  It is another thing altogether to assert that God cannot do something that is logically possible, such as preventing a person from freely doing something or knowing the outcome of all future events. There are those who, when making a free will defense will make claims such as, “once a decision is made, human experience takes one road to the exclusion of others. Until that choice is final, God cannot know the course of an individual’s life.  Free will requires and open future that would be a sham if God were prescient.  It follows that the deity lacks complete knowledge.”[45] Such a position is not required when making a free will defense. When a defense impinges upon the biblically sound concept of God as “a Spirit, infinite, eternal, and unchangeable in his being, wisdom, holiness, justice, goodness, and truth,”[46] then it ceases to be a biblically valuable Christian Apologetic.  The Christian apologist must choose his theodicies and defenses biblically.

He should also choose them wisely.  Christian Philosopher Jeremy Evans has rightly stated, “In times of suffering we usually need the comfort of friends and not the counsel of scholars.”[47]  The apologist should be careful to assess the appropriateness of pointing out the philosophical shortcomings of arguments from evil to one who is questioning God as the result of some personal calamity.  Not everyone will react to misfortune as righteously and exemplary as Job. “Intellectual arguments are not well received when the other person is involved in emotional arguments.”[48]  Biblical arguments about God’s unfailing love may be better received and are always in order.[49]

*Please note that the preceding is my personal opinion. It is not necessarily the opinion of any entity by which I am employed, any church at which I am a member, any church which I attend, or the educational institution at which I am enrolled. Any copyrighted material displayed or referenced is done under the doctrine of fair use.

BIBLIOGRAHPY

 Bowman, Rob. “How Not to Debate a Christian Apologist.” Credo House Ministries. February 28, 2014. http://www.reclaimingthemind.org/blog/2014/02/how-not-to-debate-a-christian-apologist/ (accessed March 10, 2014).

Craig, William Lane. Reasonable Faith: Christian Truth and Apologetics. Crossway Books, 2008.

—. “The Problem of Evil.” Reasonable Fath. http://www.reasonablefaith.org/the-problem-of-evil (accessed March 8, 2014).

Crenshaw, James L. Defending God: Biblical Repsonses to the Problem of Evil. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2005.

Davies, Brian. Philosophy of Religion: a Guide and Antholgy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Dunn, G. Seth. “Insuperable Good News: Overcoming the Problem of the Problem From Evil.” Submitted to Dr. Robert Stewart of the New Orleans Baptist Thelogical Seminary, January 31, 2010.

Dunn, G. Seth. Jeremy Evans’ the Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Beleifs. Submitted to Dr. Rhyne Putman of the New Orleans Baptist Theological Seminary, February 15, 2015.

Dunn, G. Seth. Michael L. Peterson’s God and Evil: An Introduction to the Issues. Submitted to Dr. Robert Stewart of the New Orleans Baptist Thelogical Seminary, January 31, 2010.

Erickson, Millard J. Christian Theology: Second Edition. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 1998.

Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013.

Gale, Richard M. “Evil and Alvin Plantinga.” In Alvin Plantiga, by Deane-Peter Baker, 49. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

Groothuis, Douglas. Christian Apologetics: A Comprehensive Case for Biblical Faith . Downers Groove, IL: IVP Academic, 2011.

Larrimore, Mark. The Book of Job: A Biography. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2013.

Lowth, Robert. Lectures on the Sacred Poetry of the Ancient Hebrews. Translated by G. Gregory. 2 vols. London: J. Johnson, 1835.

Mackie, J.L. “Evil and Omnipotence.” In Philosophy of Religion: a Guide and Anthology, by Brian Davies, 581. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Menzies, Peter. Mackie, John Leslie (1917–1981). 2012. http://adb.anu.edu.au/biography/mackie-john-leslie-14214 (accessed March 5, 2014).

Peterson, Michael L. God and Evil: An Introduction to the Issues. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press, 1998.

Plantinga, Alvin. God, Freedom, and Evil. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1978.

Sowell, Thomas. A Conflict of Visions: Idealogical Origins of Political Struggles. Basic Books, 2007.

The Presbyterian Church in America. “The Shorter Catechism.” http://www.pcaac.org . http://www.pcaac.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/11/ShorterCatechismwithScriptureProofs.pdf.

Wikiquote contributors. “Epicurus.” Wikiquote. February 18, 2014. http://en.wikiquote.org/w/index.php?title=Epicurus&oldid=1684115 (accessed March 6, 2014).

[1]Larrimore, Mark. The Book of Job: A Biography. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2013, 11

[2] Lowth, Robert. Lectures on the Sacred Poetry of the Ancient Hebrews. Translated by G. Gregory. 2 vols. London: J. Johnson, 1835, 352

[3] Job 1:13-19, 2:7-8.  (He loses his wife, too, but it’s debatable whether or not he was worse off for losing that woman.)

[4] Larrimore, Mark. The Book of Job: A Biography. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2013, 78

[5] Wikiquote contributors. Epicurus. February 18 , 2014. http://en.wikiquote.org/w/index.php?title=Epicurus&oldid=1684115

[6] There is some argument that the question should properly be attributed to Lactantius.

[7] Mackie’s exact quote is as follows: “In its simplest form, the problem of evil is this:  God is omnipotent, God is wholly good; and yet evil exists.”  The terms “Problem of Evil” and “Problem from Evil” are often used interchangeably.  To avoid confusion and because I believe it to be a better descriptor, the term “Problem from Evil” will be used in the paper.

[8] Mackie, J. “Evil and Omnipotence.” In Philosophy of Religion: a Guide and Anthology, by B. Davies, 581.

[9] The forms of these arguments, as presented in this paper, were adapted from Michael L. Peterson’s book, God and Evil

[10] 1 Pet. 3:15

[11] Groothuis, Douglas. Christian Apologetics: A Comprehensive Case for Biblical Faith . Downers Groove, IL: IVP Academic, 2011, Kindle Locations 6649-6651

[12] At least in Western thought, they do.

[13] Gale, Richard M. “Evil and Alvin Plantinga.” In Alvin Plantiga, by Deane-Peter Baker, 49. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

[14] Bowman, Rob. “How Not to Debate a Christian Apologist.” Credo House Ministries. February 28, 2014. http://www.reclaimingthemind.org/blog/2014/02/how-not-to-debate-a-christian-apologist/

[15] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013, 23

[16] Here we ignore such activities as cloud-seeding.

[17] Job 1:18-19

[18] This also raises the question, “Is natural evil always really evil?”  The flood of Noah’s day may have seemed like natural evil to those it killed.  However, it was a righteous act directly brought about by God.

[19] Rom. 5:12-14

[20] Gen. 3:19

[21] Rom. 5:3-5

[22] 1 Pet. 4:12

[23] 1 Pet. 4:19

[24] 1 Pet. 4:15-16

[25] Craig,  Willaim Lane . Reasonable Faith: Christian Truth and Apologetics. Crossway Books, 2008, 175

[26] Isa. 5:20-21

[27] Rom. 1:28-32

[28] Luke 18:19

[29] This notion is explored further in the section of this paper titled “A Biblical Response from Constraints”

[30] Jer. 5:8

[31] Jer. 5:5

[32] With the exception of God incarnate, Jesus Christ

[33] Job 38:4-5

[34] Personally, I think that the very concept of gratuitous evil could exist because God wanted to give theology students and Christian apologists a challenging thought exercise.

[35] Peterson, Michael L. God and Evil: An Introduction to the Issues. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press, 1998, 104

[36] Plantinga, Alvin. God, Freedom, and Evil. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1978, 48

[37] Craig, William Lane. “The Problem of Evil.” Reasonable Fath. http://www.reasonablefaith.org/the-problem-of-evil (accessed March 8, 2014).

[38] Sowell, Thomas. A Conflict of Visions: Idealogical Origins of Political Struggles. Basic Books, 2007, 4

[39] Gen. 1:31

[40] Gen. 2:17

[41] Gen. 3:17

[42] Erickson, Millard J. Christian Theology: Second Edition. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 1998, 452

[43] Job 1:38

[44] Isa. 55:8-9

[45] Crenshaw, James L. Defending God: Biblical Repsonses to the Problem of Evil. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2005, 76

[46] The Presbyterian Church in America. “The Shorter Catechism.” http://www.pcaac.org . http://www.pcaac.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/11/ShorterCatechismwithScriptureProofs.pdf.

[47] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013, 219

[48] McRaney Jr., Willaim. The Art of Personal Evangelism: Sharing Jesus in a Changing Culture. B&H Academic, 2003, 208

[49] 1 Cor. 13:8

Jeremy Evans’ The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Beleifs – A Review

Who is Jeremy Evans?

“Jeremy Evans is an Assistant Professor of Christian Philosophy at Southeastern Baptist Theological Seminary…He earned his Ph.D. from Texas A&M University”[1] He is author of two books, both of which are about Christian thought and philosophy.   He is a member of the Evangelical Theological Society, the Society of Christian Philosophers, and the American Philosophical Association.

Evans’ Assumptions and the Book’s Purpose

Evans opens The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief (the book) by stating, “Christians have generally agreed that evil is not a substance or a thing but instead is a privation of a good thing that God made.”[2]  This simple Augustinian definition of evil, that evil is not something but rather the lack of something, has been enough, in the minds of many Christians throughout the centuries, to dispatch what has become known as “The problem of Evil”.[3]  However, this definitional defense of God in the face of the supposed existence of evil has not been sufficient for more than a few thinkers; long and intense philosophical conversations have thus emerged from engaging with the problem of evil.  A number of theodicies have been developed over time to explain or invalidate the Problem of Evil.  In the book, Evans explores and explains (without endorsing) a number of these theodicies.  In his opinion, “no one theodicy suffices to answer the problem of evil…each theodicy has its application in particular domains of the conversation.”[4]  These various theodicies address various, specific, problems from evil.[5] Those well-educated in the subject of theodicies understand that certain venerable theodicies are not congruent with the biblical text.  Evans’ writing on such theodicies, though, shows faithfulness to the biblical text.  As a member of the Evangelical Philosophical Society, Evans affirms that, “the Bible alone, and the Bible in its entirety, is the Word of God written and therefore inerrant in the original manuscripts. God is a Trinity: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, each an uncreated person, one in essence, equal in power and glory.”[6]  His purpose in writing the book seems clear and simple: explore the problem of evil from a biblically-based philosophical perspective.

A Summary

The book is written in a progressive format.  Evans first dedicates a chapter to introducing the basic issues of the broad, general Problem of Evil (such as the difference between natural evil and moral evil).  He then dedicates middle-chapters to addressing various, more specific problems from evil and their defeat.  After doing so, he dedicates a section of his book to comparing theism with naturalism in the face of evil.  Finally, Evans addresses morality and evil in light of God’s nature, thus providing a comprehensive overview of the Problem of Evil.

In addition to using it to distinguish between moral evil and natural evil, Evans uses Chapter One to differentiate between theodicies for God, which are offensive in nature, and defenses of God.  There are four theodicies which Evans summarizes in this chapter: the Punishment Theodicy, the Free-Will Theodicy, the Natural-Law Theodicy, and the Soul-Making Theodicy.   Evans provides scriptural support for the Punishment Theodicy and the Free-Will Theodicy.   He does not do so for the latter two theodicies, which are more strictly philosophical in nature.

The first specific Problem of Evil that Evans addresses is the Logical Problem of Evil, most notably formulated by atheist philosopher J.L. Mackie.  As Evans notes, Mackie “decidedly rejected his own thesis in his later work, effectually conceding that the problem of evil does not show that the central doctrines of theism are logically inconsistent with one another given the reality of evil”[7].  This rejection was done in light of the, now famous[8], Free-Will Defense presented by Alvin Plantinga.  The existence of human freedom (as granted by God) Plantinga argues, shows that it is logically possible for evil to exist in a world where God exists.  Mackie is not the only one who has rejected his thesis.  “It is almost universally agreed that evil is logically compatible with the existence of God.”[9]  There is another problem from evil, however, that imparts a powerful and more visceral reaction on the one who considers it.  This problem, the Evidential Problem of Evil, argues that “the pervasiveness of evil makes it less likely that God exists,” is the next problem from evil that Evans’ addresses.[10]  This argument is popularly known as the “Bambi” argument.  Its basic premise is that there are some events that are so gratuitously evil, such as the slow death of a fawn burned alive in a forest fire, that there is no conceivable greater good that can be imagined which can result from their happenings.  If God existed, goes the argument, He (being omniscient and omnipotent) would prevent such gratuitous evil.  Critics of this argument point out major failures with this premise.  The premise involves a non-omniscient being stating what an omniscient being would do in a given situation.  God’s thoughts and ways, according to the prophet Isaiah, are higher than those of man.[11]  Furthermore, a non-omniscient being’s limitations are such that he cannot definitely proclaim any evil to be gratuitous.  He simply can’t know that evil is gratuitous.  The flaws in the Evidential Problem of Evil…are evident.  Both the logically and evidential arguments are defeated.  The discussion of this “defeat of evil” as Evans’ calls it, is manifested in the existence of human free will, which is “a sufficient reason for God’s permission of evil”[12] and the explanation of why evil exists.  Given an explanation of why evil exists, humankind is left with the question of what to do about it.  Evans’ response is that humans “should partner with God”[13] in order to gain the ability to overcome evil.

Of course, to partner with God, one must first find him.   Friedrich Nietzsche asked, “A god who is all-knowing and all-powerful and who does not even make sure his creatures understand his intention— could that be a god of goodness?[14]  Nietzsche’s words epitomize a problem from Evil known as Divine Hiddenness, which Evans’ addresses in Chapter Five of the book.  An argument from Divine Hiddenness asserts that if God existed, His existence would be so apparent that men would not reasonably doubt that existences; yet, men do.   Like the Evidential Problem, to refute such an argument one must either show that (1) God’s existence must not necessarily be readily apparent or (2) it is not reasonable to doubt God because of apparent hiddenness.  Like the Evidential Problem, the argument from Divine Hiddenness dies upon the sword of human imperfection.  Where God is holy, man is sinful.  God’s holiness drives the “hiddenness” that separates Him from men.  Furthermore, the noetic effects of sin cause man to fail to recognize what is apparent about God’s nature.  Ultimately, God has shown himself to man through His incarnation in Jesus Christ.  In Christ, God has dwelt with man in flesh.  However, even though God has come in the flesh, there remain those who will be separated from God for an eternity in Hell.  The Problem of Hell is the next problem which Evans addresses in the book.  Surely if God were good, according to the Problem of Hell, God wouldn’t send people there for eternity.  Yet, He does.  Some have argued, through universalism or annihilationism, that He does not.  Evans explores such arguments but ultimately concludes that hell is a just divine response to human sinfulness. “Hell is not what hardens a person; instead, hell is a place for hardened persons.”[15]

Evans’ moves on to what could rightly be described as “the problem of naturalism” in Chapter Seven.  The purpose of this particular chapter is “to offer a more coherent concept of the idea of natural evil,”[16] in accordance with Evans’ assertion that “many things often called natural evil do not rightly fit in that category.”[17]  He undergirds his exploration of that purpose with a criticism of theism’s antithesis, naturalism. Citing work done by the venerable Christian apologist, Paul Copan, Evan’s points out to the reader than the existence of anything at all, especially a universe that permits, produces, and sustains life, is astronomically[18] unlikely on naturalism.  Whatever objections one may have to natural evil inside of a Christian or even generically theistic worldview pale in comparison to the simple reality that naturalism abjectly fails to explain the existence of the natural world at all.

In Chapter Eight, Evan’s shifts focus from what he deems “the more traditional issues attending the problem of evil”[19] by considering what he considers to be a more contemporary philosophical problem from evil, The Deontological Problem of Evil.  He delineates for the reader the difference between axiological arguments from evil, which consider the merits and goodness and badness itself, and deontological arguments from evil, which focus on the rightness and wrongness of actions.  Deontological arguments from evil consider the duty of God, asserting that the existence of certain heinous states of affairs indicate that an omnipotent and omnibenevolent being who has the moral duty and power to prevent such states of affairs does not exist.  This argument comes across as a modified hybrid of the logical and evidential problems of evil.  It similarly fails in that human limitations do not permit a man to conclude that a certain state of affairs is so heinous that God had a duty to prevent it.  Not content to refute the Deontological Argument from Evil in this manner, Evans asserts that God has no duties at all.  God’s existence, Evans asserts, provides the very foundation to ground goodness and duty.  He fleshes out this assertion in Chapter Nine.  In order for evil to exist objectively, there must be an objective standard in which to ground goodness; God’s nature is the only sufficient objective standard in which to ground goodness.  Again citing a venerable apologist, this time William Lane Craig[20], and again demonstrating the impotence of the explanatory power of naturalism, Evan’s logically shows that the existence of evil[21] indicates the existence of God.  To even reasonably consider that moral values and duties exist, one must affirm that God exists to objectively grounds such objective moral value and duties.  As the very grounding of duties, God does not have moral duties to those in whom duties cannot be objectively grounded.  The moral duties of God’s creations to fulfill His commands are grounded in the fealty His creations owe God.  God, on the hand, has no moral obligations to anyone except Himself.

In Chapter Eleven, Evans fleshes the relationship between God’s commands and His will in order to help the reader better understand the nature of how moral obligations about come.  This chapter addresses the in-and-outs of duties themselves and therefore only tangentially deals with the Problem of Evil.  Chapter 12, which is addresses the Worship-Worthiness of God also does not directly address the Problem of Evil.  It does, however, consider the theological danger of abandoning a commitment to one of God’s attributes in order to subvert an objection to God’s existence from the Problem of Evil (for example, abandoning God’s omniscience to refute the Deontological Problem of Evil).  An imperfect God is not necessarily a god who should be worshiped.  Throughout the book’s previous Chapters, Evan’s argues from God’s perfect nature, never abandoning an attribute of God to escape a trap set by the purveyor of the Problem of Evil.  Evans asserts that a being with such a perfect nature is worthy of worship.  Evan’s ,citing Acts 17:28, states, “the very fact that God is Creator and Sustainer of every contingent being warrants praise in itself; ‘in him we live move and have our being’…The debt of existence is no small debt, and God’s acts of creation and offering of reconciliation are manifestations of his supererogation.”[22]

Analysis and Evaluation

In the conclusion to his book, Evans makes two poignant observations.  The first is that evil is, ironically, evidence for the existence of God rather than against it.   The second is that providing such a logical response to the problem of evil may not fulfill the need of someone who is undergoing suffering and considering the existence of God in the face of evil.  “In times of suffering,” Evans states, “we usually need the comfort of friends and not the counsel of scholars.”[23]  This is prudent admission, especially from a scholar who has done such a comprehensive job of addressing the Problem of Evil.  Given the ample treatment that Evans provides of the Problem of Evil, the Book is exactly what it advertises itself to be and does an excellent job of addressing the most common and enduring problems from evil.  Its concluding chapters are indicative of the extensive treatment these problems have already received in the realm of Christian academia.  These chapters, excluding Chapter 12, appear to address the more “contemporary” philosophical issues of an ancient problem for the sake of providing enough “new” material to justify the publication of a book on a subject that has been written on many times in the past.  The inclusion of these chapters, however, is hardly inappropriate given the subject matter and does not take away from the overall quality and usefulness of the book.   One who has engaged with the problem of evil by reading an introductory volume on the subject such as “God and Evil: An Introduction to the Issues” by Michael L Peterson would be well-served to ingest Evan’s book if he is looking for a meatier treatment of the Problem of Evil.  It’s a good one.

 SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

Evangelical Philosophical Society. Membership – Evangelical Philosophical Society. 2015. http://www.epsociety.org/about/membership.asp (accessed January 5, 2015).

Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013.

Seminary, Southeastern Baptist Theological. Evans, Jeremy A. http://www.sebts.edu/academics/faculty/ (accessed January 31, 2015).

Society, Evangelical Philosophical. Jeremy Evans, PhD. 2015. http://www.epsociety.org/library/authors.asp?mode=profile&pid=39 (accessed February 2015, 2015).

[1] Society, Evangelical Philosophical. Jeremy Evans, PhD. 2015. http://www.epsociety.org/library/authors.asp?mode=profile&pid=39 (accessed February 2015, 2015).

[2] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013. p.1

[3] According to philosopher J.L. Mackie, “In its simplest form the problem of evil is this:  God is omnipotent, God is wholly good; and yet evil exists.”  The terms “Problem of Evil” and “Problem from Evil” are often used interchangeably.  See Mackie, J. “Evil and Omnipotence.” In Philosophy of Religion: a Guide and Anthology, by B. Davies, 581.

[4] Ibid p.14

[5] As noted in footnote three, the Problem of Evil is the general idea that the existence of evil and God are contradictory.  “Problems from evil” are specific formulations of the Problem of Evil which attempt to explain why the co-existence of God and evil are incompatible.

[6] Evangelical Philosophical Society. Membership – Evangelical Philosophical Society. 2015. http://www.epsociety.org/about/membership.asp (accessed January 5, 2015).

[7] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013. p.22

[8] Among philosophers, theologians, and Christian apologists.

[9] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013. p.23

[10] ibid

[11] Isa 55:9

[12] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013. p.58

[13] Ibid p. 58

[14] Ibid p. 61

[15] Ibid 102

[16] Ibid p. 68

[17] Ibid p. 68

[18] I use this term in that sense that it refers to something very large, not as it relates to astronomy iteself

[19] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013. p. 133

[20] Evans cites a version of Craig’s deductive moral argument which in its simplest form, a modus tollens, goes as follows: 1. If God does not exist, objective moral values do not exist. 2. Objective moral values exist. 3. Therefore, God exists.

[21] or at least a state of affairs in which it is reasonable to deem that there exists a privation of good

[22] Evans, Jeremy A. The Problem of Evil: The Challenge to Essential Christian Belief. B & H Academic, 2013.  p. 215

[23] Ibid p. 219

*Please note that the preceding is my personal opinion. It is not necessarily the opinion of any entity by which I am employed, any church at which I am a member, any church which I attend, or the educational institution at which I am enrolled. Any copyrighted material displayed or referenced is done under the doctrine of fair use.

Car Keys, Food, Dogs, and Other Things that God Doesn’t Need

“The God who made the world and all things in it, since He is Lord of heaven and earth, does not dwell in temples made with hands; nor is He served by human hands, as though He needed anything, since He Himself gives to all people life and breath and all things.” – Paul speaking to the Athenians as recorded in Acts 17:24-25

About two weeks ago, I lost my wallet.  Last night, I resolved that I would either find my lost wallet this morning or start down the long road of replacing its contents. After I put my children down for their 10 AM nap, I started the search for my wallet in the car. As I did so, I paused to pray two things: (1) “Lord, help me find my wallet” and (2) “Lord, forgive me for not searching harder for it sooner.” Shortly thereafter, I found my wallet in the pocket of the slacks I had been wearing on the day I lost it.  I had already looked there but apparently not well enough. You can imagine the grievous inconveniences I would have had to endure had I not managed to find my wallet.  The events of the morning brought to my mind a meme an atheist friend recently posted to her Facebook feed.  It was very similar to this one:

ImageShould I not have prayed to find my wallet in deference to larger problems in the world?  Did God really answer my prayer to find my wallet while He let some starving African child die of deprivation?  Maybe He did, but so what?  It seems that the atheist who created this meme clearly misunderstands the character and nature of the God in whom he claims not to believe.  The events portrayed in this meme should not be considered from man’s perspective, but from God’s.  Let’s take a look:

  1. The African child may need food more immediately then I need my wallet, but God doesn’t need either of these things.  Wallets (and their contents) are of no more value to God than food.  God doesn’t need anything, including me or the African child.
  2. It takes no more of God’s power to cause someone to find his lost keys that it does for Him to part the Red Sea or make bread rain from the sky. From God’s perspective, one miracle is not greater than the next in scope.
  3. My car and my wallet are tools to help me obtain the very thing, food, which the starving African goes without.  We live in a fallen world; this is the very reason people starve.  There would be no death at all if it were not for the fall of man in the Garden of Eden.  People would eat but they would not toil, to any degree, to obtain food.  No one would need a car to drive to the grocery store to buy food or to drive to work to earn money to pay for food.  If there were any need at all for cars in an edenic world, there would be no need for car keys or wallets because there would be no theft or money.
  4. I likely wouldn’t die of starvation if I didn’t find my wallet.  Chances are someone in the third world did die of starvation today.  I will eventually die, however, and I will be just as dead as the starving African.  As we see from the biblical account, God holds power over death.   One day God will raise everyone who has ever died from the dead.  A death on this earth is not final for any man.

Recently, my friend, Mark, and I attended an apologetics conference in New Orleans.  It’s the kind of conference where we talk about stuff like the 4 points above.  In the middle of the week, Mark received a call from his wife and daughter in Atlanta.  His dog, Collin, was lost.  I won’t ever forget the look on his face.  Up until then, we had been having a really good time, but upon hearing the news about his dog, Mark’s countenance fell.  He was miles away from his family.  He couldn’t look for the dog and he couldn’t comfort his family in person.  I could tell it was hurting him.  What could he do?  He posted on social media to get the word out and he prayed.  So did I.  “Dear Lord, please bring back Mark’s dog” It was the first thing I did upon hearing the news.  God, who has no need of pets, heard my prayer.

I’ll continue to pray for what’s lost, not merely in the hopes of receiving material provision but out of Love for God…I love God and I need Him. That is why I pray.  I have a spiritual need.

Man’s needs are not ultimately physical in nature; they are spiritual.  We are spiritual beings.  God’s provision, therefore, is not ultimately expressed in providing physical sustenance.  That’s why the second prayer I prayed to God this morning was the more important one.  I had been a poor steward of the property which God had entrusted to me.  I had lost some very important things for two weeks and barely bothered to search for them.  That was a failure on my part. God provided me something much more important than the contents of my wallet.  He provided forgiveness.  This is a spiritual need.

God offers forgiveness eternally in the free gift of Jesus Christ.  If you do not know Christ as your savior today, you are lost in your spirit.  Because I pray for what is lost, I am praying that you fill find your rest in the promises of Jesus Christ.

“For God so loved the world, that He gave His only begotten Son, that whoever believes in Him shall not perish, but have eternal life.” – The Lord Jesus to Nicodemus the Pharisee as recorded in John 3:16